From the book ‘The Silence of Animals’ by John Gray:
HUMANISM AND FLYING SAUCERS
If
belief in human rationality was a scientific theory it would long since
have been abandoned. A striking falsification can be found in a classic
of social psychology, When Prophecy Fails (1956), a study of a UFO cult
in the early 1950s. Written by a team led by Leon Festinger, the
psychologist who developed the idea of cognitive dissonance, the book
recounts how a Michigan woman claimed to have received messages in
automatic writing from alien intelligences on another planet announcing
the end of the world, which would be inundated by a great flood in the
hours before dawn on 21 December 1954. The woman and her disciples had
left their homes, jobs and partners and given away their possessions, in
order to be ready for the arrival of a flying saucer that would rescue
them from the doomed planet.
For
Festinger and his colleagues, this was an opportunity to test the
theory of cognitive dissonance. According to the theory, human beings do
not deal with conflicting beliefs and perceptions by testing them
against facts. They reduce the conflict by reinterpreting facts that
challenge the beliefs to which they are most attached. As T. S. Eliot
wrote in Burnt Norton, human kind cannot bear very much reality.
In
order to test the theory, the psychologists infiltrated themselves into
the cult and observed the reaction when the apocalypse failed to occur.
Just as the theory predicted, the cultists refused to accept that their
system of beliefs was mistaken. Instead, they interpreted the failure
of doomsday to arrive as evidence that by waiting and praying throughout
the night they had succeeded in preventing it. The confounding of all
their expectations only led them to cling more tightly to their faith,
and they went on to proselytize for their beliefs all the more
fervently. As Festinger writes, summarizing this process:
Suppose
an individual believes something with his whole heart; suppose further
that he has a commitment to this belief, that he has taken irrevocable
actions because of it; finally, suppose that he is presented with
evidence, unequivocal and undeniable evidence, that his belief is wrong;
what will happen? The individual will frequently emerge, not only
unshaken, but even more convinced of the truth of his beliefs than ever
before. Indeed, he may even show a new fervour about convincing and
converting other people to his view.
Denying
reality in order to preserve a view of the world is not a practice
confined to cults. Cognitive dissonance is the normal human condition.
Messianic movements, whose followers live expecting the arrival of a
saviour, embody this dissonance in a pure form. As Festinger writes,
‘Ever since the crucifixion of Jesus, many Christians have hoped for the
second coming of Christ, and movements predicting specific dates have
not been rare … [Messianic believers] are convinced followers; they
commit themselves by uprooting their lives … the Second Advent does not
occur. And, we note, far from halting the movement, this disconfirmation
gives it new life.’ Apocalyptic movements need not be overtly
religious. Citing Festinger’s work, the literary critic Frank Kermode
observed that, ‘though for us the End has perhaps lost its naive
imminence, its shadow still lies on the crises of our fictions.’
The
shadow of apocalypse falls on many radical movements. Reproduced in
secular form, apocalyptic myths possessed revolutionaries from the
Jacobins to the Bolsheviks and beyond, inspiring movements as seemingly
different as Trotskyism and late twentiethcentury American
neo-conservatism. Proletarian humanity in Soviet Russia, the Übermensch
in Nazi Germany, the global producer-consumer awaited by congregations
of the rich at meetings of the World Economic Forum in Davos – any one
of these versions of humanity would have marked something new in
history. Happily, the end-time failed to arrive and none of the phantoms
materialized.
If
there is anything unique about the human animal it is that it has the
ability to grow knowledge at an accelerating rate while being
chronically incapable of learning from experience. Science and
technology are cumulative, whereas ethics and politics deal with
recurring dilemmas. Whatever they are called, torture and slavery are
universal evils; but these evils cannot be consigned to the past like
redundant theories in science. They return under different names:
torture as enhanced interrogation techniques, slavery as human
trafficking. Any reduction in universal evils is an advance in
civilization. But, unlike scientific knowledge, the restraints of
civilized life cannot be stored on a computer disc. They are habits of
behaviour, which once broken are hard to mend. Civilization is natural
for humans, but so is barbarism.
The
evidence of science and history is that humans are only ever partly and
intermittently rational, but for modern humanists the solution is
simple: human beings must in future be more reasonable. These
enthusiasts for reason have not noticed that the idea that humans may
one day be more rational requires a greater leap of faith than anything
in religion. Since it requires a miraculous breach in the order of
things, the idea that Jesus returned from the dead is not as contrary to
reason as the notion that human beings will in future be different from
how they have always been.
In
the most general terms, humanism is the idea that the human animal is
the site of some kind of unique value in the world. The philosophers of
ancient Greece believed that humans were special in having a capacity
for reason lacking in other animals, and some of these philosophers –
notably Socrates, at least as he is described by Plato – believed that
through the use of reason humans could access a spiritual realm. A
related aspect of humanism is the idea that the human mind reflects the
order of the cosmos. The spiritual realm in which Socrates may have
believed was composed of timeless forms – in other words, metaphysical
projections of human concepts. A third aspect of humanism is the idea
that history is a story of human advance, with rationality increasing
over time. This is a distinctively modern view, nowhere found among the
wiser thinkers of the ancient world.
Not
everyone who is described as a humanist has accepted these ideas. The
sixteenthcentury essayist Michel de Montaigne has been seen as a
humanist because he turned to classical learning and a life of
self-cultivation. But Montaigne mocked the belief that humans are
superior to other animals, rejected the notion that the human mind
mirrors the world and ridiculed the idea that it is reason that enables
humans to live well. There is no trace in him of the belief in progress
that would later shape modern humanism. As a good sceptic, Montaigne
left open the window to faith. But there is nothing in his writings of
the mystical ideas that underpin assertions of human uniqueness in
Socrates and Plato.
Humanists
today, who claim to take a wholly secular view of things, scoff at
mysticism and religion. But the unique status of humans is hard to
defend, and even to understand, when it is cut off from any idea of
transcendence. In a strictly naturalistic view – one in which the world
is taken on its own terms, without reference to a creator or any
spiritual realm – there is no hierarchy of value with humans at the top.
There are simply multifarious animals, each with their own needs. Human
uniqueness is a myth inherited from religion, which humanists have
recycled into science.
The
hostility of humanists to myth is telling, since if anything is
peculiarly human it is myth-making. Every human culture is animated by
myth, in some degree, while no other animal displays anything similar.
Humanists are also ruled by myths, though the ones by which they are
possessed have none of the beauty or the wisdom of those that they
scorn. The myth that human beings can use their minds to lift themselves
out of the natural world, which in Socrates and Plato was part of a
mystical philosophy, has been renewed in a garbled version of the
language of evolution.
There
is little in the current fad for evolutionary theories of society that
cannot be found, sometimes more clearly expressed, in the writings of
Herbert Spencer, the Victorian prophet of what would later be called
Social Darwinism. Believing the human history was itself a kind of
evolutionary process, Spencer asserted that the end-point of the process
was laissezfaire capitalism. His disciples Sidney and Beatrice Webb,
early members of the Fabian Society and admirers of the Soviet Union,
believed it culminated in communism. Aiming to be more judicious, a
later generation of theorists has nominated ‘democratic capitalism’ as
the terminus. As might have been foreseen, none of these consummations
has come to pass.
The
most important feature of natural selection is that it is a process of
drift. Evolution has no end-point or direction, so if the development of
society is an evolutionary process it is one that is going nowhere. The
destinations that successive generations of theorists have assigned to
evolution have no basis in science. Invariably, they are the prevailing
idea of progress recycled in Darwinian terms.
As
refined by later scientists, Darwin’s theory posits the natural
selection of random genetic mutations. In contrast, no one has come up
with a unit of selection or a mechanism through which evolution operates
in society. On an evolutionary view the human mind has no built-in bias
to truth or rationality and will continue to develop according to the
imperative of survival. Theories of human rationality increasing through
social evolution are as groundless today as they were when Spencer used
them to promote laissez-faire capitalism and the Webbs communism.
Reviving long-exploded errors, twenty-first-century believers in
progress unwittingly demonstrate the unreality of progress in the
history of ideas.
For
humanists, denying that humanity can live without myths can only be a
type of pessimism. They take for granted that if human beings came to be
more like the rational figments they have in mind, the result would be
an improvement. Leave aside the assumption – itself very questionable –
that a rational life must be one without myths. Rational or not, life
without myth is like life without art or sex – insipid and inhuman. The
actuality, with all its horrors, is preferable. Luckily a choice need
not be made, since the life of reason that humanists anticipate is only a
fantasy.
If
there is a choice it is between myths. In comparison with the Genesis
myth, the modern myth in which humanity is marching to a better future
is mere superstition. As the Genesis story teaches, knowledge cannot
save us from ourselves. If we know more than before, it means only that
we have greater scope to enact our fantasies. But – as the Genesis myth
also teaches – there is no way we can rid ourselves of what we know. If
we try to regain a state of innocence, the result can only be a worse
madness. The message of Genesis is that in the most vital areas of human
life there can be no progress, only an unending struggle with our own
nature.
When
contemporary humanists invoke the idea of progress they are mixing
together two different myths: a Socratic myth of reason and a Christian
myth of salvation. If the resulting body of ideas is incoherent, that is
the source of its appeal. Humanists believe that humanity improves
along with the growth of knowledge, but the belief that the increase of
knowledge goes with advances in civilization is an act of faith. They
see the realization of human potential as the goal of history, when
rational inquiry shows history to have no goal. They exalt nature, while
insisting that humankind – an accident of nature – can overcome the
natural limits that shape the lives of other animals. Plainly absurd,
this nonsense gives meaning to the lives of people who believe they have
left all myths behind.
To
expect humanists to give up their myths would be unreasonable. Like
cheap music, the myth of progress lifts the spirits as it numbs the
brain. The fact that rational humanity shows no sign of ever arriving
only makes humanists cling more fervently to the conviction that
humankind will someday be redeemed from unreason. Like believers in
flying saucers, they interpret the non-event as confirming their faith.
Science and
the idea of progress may seem joined together, but the end-result of
progress in science is to show the impossibility of progress in
civilization. Science is a solvent of illusion, and among the illusions
it dissolves are those of humanism. Human knowledge increases, while
human irrationality stays the same. Scientific inquiry may be an
embodiment of reason, but what such inquiry demonstrates is that humans
are not rational animals. The fact that humanists refuse to accept the
demonstration only confirms its truth.
Atheism
and humanism may also seem to be conjoined when in fact they are at
odds. Among contemporary atheists, disbelief in progress is a type of
blasphemy. Pointing to the flaws of the human animal has become an act
of sacrilege. The decline of religion has only stiffened the hold of
faith on the mind. Unbelief today should begin by questioning not
religion but secular faith. A type of atheism that refused to revere
humanity would be a genuine advance. Freud’s thought exemplifies atheism
of this kind; but Freud has been rejected precisely because he refused
to flatter the human animal. It is not surprising that atheism remains a
humanist cult. To suppose that the myth of progress could be shaken off
would be to ascribe to modern humanity a capacity for improvement even
greater than that which it ascribes to itself.
Modern
myths are myths of salvation stated in secular terms. What both kinds
of myths have in common is that they answer to a need for meaning that
cannot be denied. In order to survive, humans have invented science.
Pursued consistently, scientific inquiry acts to undermine myth. But
life without myth is impossible, so science has become a channel for
myths – chief among them, a myth of salvation through science. When
truth is at odds with meaning, it is meaning that wins. Why this should
be so is a delicate question. Why is meaning so important? Why do humans
need a reason to live? Is it because they could not endure life if they
did not believe it contained hidden significance? Or does the demand
for meaning come from attaching too much sense to language – from
thinking that our lives are books we have not yet learnt to read?